2173 Salk Avenue, Suite 250 Carlsbad, CA

support@assignmentprep.info

Please write a two-page (600-650 words) summary on Chapter 2 of Christianity:

June 15, 2021
Christopher R. Teeple

Please write a two-page (600-650 words) summary on Chapter 2 of Christianity: An introduction (The Christian Bible), which focuses on the Old and New Testament. (250 words summary, 350 words reflection)
Chapter2:
If they are the foundation, I had better stop to make that foundation firm before I go on. Some of the
letters I have had show that a good many people find it difficult to understand just what this Law of
Human Nature, or Moral Law, or Rule of Decent Behaviour is.
For example, some people wrote to me saying, ‘Isn’t what you call the Moral Law simply our herd
instinct and hasn’t it been developed just like all our other instincts?’ Now I do not deny that we may have
a herd instinct: but that is not what I mean by the Moral Law. We all know what it feels like to be
prompted by instinct–by mother love, or sexual instinct, or the instinct for food. It means that you feel a
strong want or desire to act in a certain way. And, of course, we sometimes do feel just that sort of desire
to help another person: and no doubt that desire is due to the herd instinct. But feeling a desire to help is
quite different from feeling that you ought to help whether you want to or not. Supposing you hear a cry for
help from a man in danger. You will probably feel two desires–one a desire to give help (due to your herd
instinct), the other a desire to keep out of danger (due to the instinct for self-preservation). But you will
find inside you, in addition to these two impulses, a third thing which tells you that you ought to follow the
impulse to help, and suppress the impulse to run away. Now this thing that judges between two instincts,
that decides which should be encouraged, cannot itself be either of them. You might as well say that the
sheet of music which tells you, at a given moment, to play one note on the piano and not another, is itself
one of the notes on the keyboard. The Moral Law tells us the tune we have to play: our instincts are
merely the keys.
Another way of seeing that the Moral Law is not simply one of our instincts is this. If’ two instincts
are in conflict, and there is nothing in a creature’s mind except those two instincts, obviously the stronger
of’ the two must win. But at those moments when we are most conscious of the Moral Law, it usually
seems to be telling us to side with the weaker of the two impulses. You probably want to be safe much
more than you want to help the man who is drowning: but the Moral Law tells you to help him all the
same. And surely it often tells us to try to make the right impulse stronger than it naturally is? I mean, we
often feel it our duty to stimulate the herd instinct, by waking up our imaginations and arousing our pity
and so on, so as to get up enough steam for doing the right thing. But clearly we are not acting from
instinct when we set about making an instinct stronger than it is. The thing that says to you, ‘Your herd
instinct is asleep. Wake it up,’ cannot itself be the herd instinct. The thing that tells you which note on the
piano needs to be played louder cannot itself be that note.
Here is a third way of seeing it. If the Moral Law was one of our instincts, we ought to be able to
point to some one impulse inside us which was always what we call ‘ good,’ always in agreement with
the rule of right behaviour. But you cannot. There is none of our impulses which the Moral Law may not
sometimes tell us to suppress, and none which it may not sometimes tell us to encourage. It is a mistake to
think that some of our impulses–say mother love or patriotism–are good, and others, like sex or the
fighting instinct, are bad. All we mean is that the occasions on which the fighting instinct or the sexual
desire need to be restrained are rather more frequent than those for restraining mother love or patriotism.
But there are situations in which it is the duty of a married man to encourage his sexual impulse and of a
soldier to encourage the fighting instinct. There are also occasions on which a mother’s love for her own
children or a man’s love for his own country have to be suppressed or they will lead to unfairness
towards other people’s children or countries. Strictly speaking, there are no such things as good and bad
impulses. Think once again of a piano. It has not got two kind of notes on it, the ‘right’ notes and the
‘wrong’ ones. Every single note is right at one time and wrong at another. The Moral Law is not any one
instinct or any set of instincts: it is something which makes a kind of tune (the tune we call goodness or
right conduct) by directing the instincts.
By the way, this point is of great practical consequence. The most dangerous thing you can do is to
take any one impulse of your own nature and set it up as the thing you ought to follow at all costs. There is
not one of them which will not make us into devils if we set it up as an absolute guide. You might think
love of humanity in general was safe, but it is not. If you leave out justice you will find yourself breaking
agreements and faking evidence in trials ‘for the sake of humanity,’ and become in the end a cruel and
treacherous man.
Other people wrote to me saying, ‘Isn’t what you call the Moral Law just a social convention,
something that is put into us by education?’ I think there is a misunderstanding here. The people who ask
that question are usually taking it for granted that if we have learned a thing from parents and teachers,
then that thing must be merely a human invention. But, of course, that is not so. We all learned the
multiplication table at school. A child who grew up alone on a desert island would not know it. But surely
it does not follow that the multiplication table is simply a human convention, something human beings
have made up for themselves and might have made different if they had liked? I fully agree that we learn
the Rule of Decent Behaviour from parents and teachers, and friends and books, as we learn everything
else. But some of the things we learn are mere conventions which might have been different–we learn to
keep to the left of the road, but it might just as well have been the rule to keep to the right–and others of
them, like mathematics, are real truths. The question is to which class the Law of Human Nature belongs.
There are two reasons for saying it belongs to the same class as mathematics. The first is, as I said in
the first chapter, that though there are differences between the moral ideas of one time or country and
those of another, the differences are not really very great–not nearly so great as most people imagine–and
you can recognise the same law running through them all: whereas mere conventions, like the rule of the
road or the kind of clothes people wear, may differ to any extent. The other reason is this. When you think
about these differences between the morality of one people and another, do you think that the morality of
one people is ever better or worse than that of another? Have any of the changes been improvements? If
not, then of course there could never be any moral progress. Progress means not just changing, but
changing for the better. If no set of moral ideas were truer or better than any other, there would be no
sense in preferring civilised morality to savage morality, or Christian morality to Nazi morality. In fact, of
course, we all do believe that some moralities are better than others. We do believe that some of the
people who tried to change the moral ideas of their own age were what we would call Reformers or
Pioneers–people who understood morality better than their neighbours did. Very well then. The moment
you say that one set of moral ideas can be better than another, you are, in fact, measuring them both by a
standard, saying that one of them conforms to that standard more nearly than the other. But the standard
that measures two things is something different from either. You are, in fact, comparing them both with
some Real Morality, admitting that there is such a thing as a real Right, independent of what people think,
and that some people’s ideas get nearer to that real Right than others. Or put it this way. If your moral
ideas can be truer, and those of the Nazis less true, there must be something-some Real Morality–for them
to be true about. The reason why your idea of New York can be truer or less true than mine is that New
York is a real place, existing quite apart from what either of us thinks. If when each of us said ‘New York’
each means merely ‘The town I am imagining in my own head,’ how could one of us have truer ideas than
the other? There would be no question of truth or falsehood at all. In the same way, if the Rule of Decent
Behaviour meant simply ‘whatever each nation happens to approve,’ there would be no sense in saying
that any one nation had ever been more correct in its approval than any other; no sense in saying that the
world could ever grow morally better or morally worse.
I conclude then, that though the differences between people’s ideas of Decent Behaviour often make
you suspect that there is no real natural Law of Behaviour at all, yet the things we are bound to think about
these differences really prove just the opposite. But one word before I end. I have met people who
exaggerate the differences, because they have not distinguished between differences of morality and
differences of belief about facts. For example, one man said to me, ‘Three hundred years ago people in
England were putting witches to death. Was that what you call the Rule of Human Nature or Right
Conduct?’ But surely the reason we do not execute witches is that we do not believe there are such things.
If we did–if we really thought that there were people going about who had sold themselves to the devil
and received supernatural powers from him in return and were using these powers to kill their neighbours
or drive them mad or bring bad weather–surely we would all agree that if anyone deserved the death
penalty, then these filthy quislings did? There is no difference of moral principle here: the difference is
simply about matter of fact. It may be a great advance in knowledge not to believe in witches: there is no
moral advance in not executing them when you do not think they are there. You would not call a man
humane for ceasing to set mousetraps if he did so because he believed there were no mice in the house.

Struggling With a Similar Paper? Get Reliable Help Now.

Delivered on time. Plagiarism-free. Good Grades.

What is this?

It’s a homework service designed by a team of 23 writers based in Carlsbad, CA with one specific goal – to help students just like you complete their assignments on time and get good grades!

Why do you do it?

Because getting a degree is hard these days! With many students being forced to juggle between demanding careers, family life and a rigorous academic schedule. Having a helping hand from time to time goes a long way in making sure you get to the finish line with your sanity intact!

How does it work?

You have an assignment you need help with. Instead of struggling on this alone, you give us your assignment instructions, we select a team of 2 writers to work on your paper, after it’s done we send it to you via email.

What kind of writer will work on my paper?

Our support team will assign your paper to a team of 2 writers with a background in your degree – For example, if you have a nursing paper we will select a team with a nursing background. The main writer will handle the research and writing part while the second writer will proof the paper for grammar, formatting & referencing mistakes if any.

Our team is comprised of native English speakers working exclusively from the United States. 

Will the paper be original?

Yes! It will be just as if you wrote the paper yourself! Completely original, written from your scratch following your specific instructions.

Is it free?

No, it’s a paid service. You pay for someone to work on your assignment for you.

Is it legit? Can I trust you?

Completely legit, backed by an iron-clad money back guarantee. We’ve been doing this since 2007 – helping students like you get through college.

Will you deliver it on time?

Absolutely! We understand you have a really tight deadline and you need this delivered a few hours before your deadline so you can look at it before turning it in.

Can you get me a good grade? It’s my final project and I need a good grade.

Yes! We only pick projects where we are sure we’ll deliver good grades.

What do you need to get started on my paper?

* The full assignment instructions as they appear on your school account.

* If a Grading Rubric is present, make sure to attach it.

* Include any special announcements or emails you might have gotten from your Professor pertaining to this assignment.

* Any templates or additional files required to complete the assignment.

How do I place an order?

You can do so through our custom order page here or you can talk to our live chat team and they’ll guide you on how to do this.

How will I receive my paper?

We will send it to your email. Please make sure to provide us with your best email – we’ll be using this to communicate to you throughout the whole process.

Getting Your Paper Today is as Simple as ABC

No more missed deadlines! No more late points deductions!

}

You give us your assignments instructions via email or through our order page.

Our support team selects a qualified writing team of 2 writers for you.

l

In under 5 minutes after you place your order, research & writing begins.

Complete paper is delivered to your email before your deadline is up.

Want A Good Grade?

Get a professional writer who has worked on a similar assignment to do this paper for you